Ethics @ Work: Tit for tat in bank secrecy

Germany is complicit in breaking Swiss law – which it views as complicit in breaking German law.

Money Shekels bills 521 (photo credit: Courtesy)
Money Shekels bills 521
(photo credit: Courtesy)
A few days ago the Julius Baer saga came to an end, as the private Swiss bank agreed to pay about 50 million euros to the German government to settle charges that the bank aided German depositors in evading taxes in Germany.
According to the settlement, the bank does not admit any wrongdoing and Germany will not pursue charges against the bank or its employees.
The most interesting ethical wrinkle in this story is the extent to which the case against Baer was built on evidence that was illegally obtained.
The first evidence came to light in 2008 in documents leaked to WikiLeaks by Baer employee Rudolf Elmer. Much of the data disclosed by Elmer was confidential, and Elmer was convicted in Switzerland for some of his disclosures. (The bank claims that some of the document are also forged.) Subsequently in 2010, the German government made a controversial step in purchasing documents that had been stolen from Baer.
What are the limits on using illegal means to obtain evidence, or on using evidence obtained by illegal means? It is useful in this regard to distinguish three levels of complicity: The most severe level is evidence obtained by illegal acts of the authorities: When the authorities themselves breach the law, for example by searching without a valid warrant, the evidence is typically not admissible in court. The “exclusionary rule” applies in this case. The concern is that without this rule, the police will have an excessive incentive to violate citizens’ rights in obtaining evidence, and that it is difficult to hold law enforcements agents accountable for their actions.
The least severe level is where the disclosure was illegal but without any government complicity. If a private citizen like Rudolf Elmer decides, for his own reasons, to disclose evidence of wrongdoing the government has no obligation to close its eyes. Private citizens don’t have a built-in incentive to ferret out wrongdoing at any price, and furthermore there is little worry that they will escape accountability, as Elmer indeed learned. So there was no reason for the German tax authorities to refrain from combing the Wikileaks documents to examine what corroboration could be found for them.
The most perplexing dilemma is where the information was obtained privately, but there was some government complicity, as when Germany bought the stolen documents pertaining to Baer. Technically, the exclusionary rule would not apply here.
The German government did not steal the information, and they broke no German law in purchasing it. But someone who buys stolen merchandise obviously has some complicity in the crime, and indeed many German lawmakers were opposed to the very public deal by which Germany obtained the stolen disks.
There are a number of considerations we could use to weigh this ethical dilemma. One is proportionality. If vital national security interests were at stake, the justification for buying stolen data would be compelling; for the case of a single individual, much less so. In this case hundreds of individuals were involved, but given that the final settlement was a relatively paltry fifty million euros, it seems that this consideration alone would not justify complicity in having Swiss citizens break Swiss law.
Another consideration is the equity of the original law. No state feels bound to give support to the laws of another country when they consider those laws improper or detrimental to their own interests. This consideration is much more germane. Germany doesn’t have any problem with the Swiss laws governing purloining confidential information, but they have a big problem with what the Swiss law allows to be confidential in the first place. Switzerland has very strict banking secrecy laws which Germany feels are abetting Germans to break German law. There is a certain audacity for Switzerland to complain that German actions are encouraging Swiss citizens to break Swiss laws, when those Swiss laws themselves encourage Germany citizens to break the law of their own country.
The best way for countries to deal with objectionable foreign laws is through diplomacy, not through rewarding their breach. This is particularly true when the benefit from the breach is relatively small.
But the German case does have some redeeming features. One is that the case involved a large number of individuals, and German might have anticipated that it involved much more money than they ultimately found. But the main redeeming feature is the close reciprocity between the ethical problem with encouraging breaking the law and the ethical objection to the law itself, which Germany viewed as encouraging breaking their own law.